April 27 marks the birthday of Herbert Spencer, which is worth noting in several respects. He was a polymath who made important contributions in many areas, including political theory and philosophy. He achieved greater widespread popularity than any other English philosopher, and is thought to be the only philosopher to sell over a million books in his lifetime. In the famous Supreme Court case of Lochner vs. New York, the majority opinion and Oliver Wendell Holmes’ dissenting opinion both related to him.
More important to me, as someone who desires as broad a canvas for freedom as possible for society, were those he influenced. One was Albert Jay Nock, who, in the Introduction to The Man Versus The State, wrote,
Spencer maintained that the State’s interventions upon the individual should be confined to punishing those crimes against person or property…Beyond this the State should not go. All that the State can do for the best interest of society…is by way of these purely negative interventions upon the Citizen.
That view is why connections can be traced between Spencer and people like Friedrich Hayek, Murray Rothbard, William Graham Sumner, Robert Nozick, Leonard Read, and many others who saw the incomparable importance of liberty for effective, moral social cooperation. And far less important, he inspired me in the same direction, first as a relatively young economist and again in the research for my Lines of Liberty (2016).
As Spencer’s birthday approached this year, I reread The Man Versus The State, as much to enjoy his ability to turn a phrase as to renew my acquaintance with his reasoning. In doing so, I was struck in both ways by an argument in his essay, “Over-legislation,” first published 164 years ago in the Westminster Review. For those who have never read his work, or have not done so for quite some time, it is well worth reading for how adeptly it diagnoses today’s political zeitgeist as well as that of England over a century and a half ago, to remember him and those who have come after him.
The cautious thinker may reason — “If in…personal affairs, where all the conditions of the case were known to me, I have so often miscalculated, how much oftener shall I miscalculate in political affairs, where the conditions are too numerous, too widespread, too complex, too obscure to be understood…I am struck with the incompetence of my intellect to prescribe for society.”
There is a great want of this practical humility in our political conduct…while every day chronicles a failure, there every day reappears the belief that it needs but [a law] and a staff of officers to effect any end desired.
Did the State fulfill efficiently its unquestionable duties, there would be some excuse for this eagerness to assign it further duties. Were there no complaints of its faulty administration of justice…of its playing the tyrant where it should have been the protector…had we, in short, proved its efficiency as judge and defender…there would be some encouragement to hope for other benefits at its hands.
Or if…the State had proved itself a capable agent in some other department…though it has bungled in everything else, yet had it in one case done well…the sanguine would have had a colorable excuse for expecting success in a new field.
As it is, however, they seem to have read backwards the parable of the talents. Not to the agent of proved efficiency do they consign further duties, but to the negligent and blundering agent. Private enterprise has done much, and done it well...Therefore, do not trust private enterprise…trust the State. Slight the good and faithful servant, and promote the unprofitable one from one talent to ten.
Ill as government discharges its true duties, any other duties committed to it are likely to be still worse discharged. To guard its subjects against aggression, either individual or national, is a straightforward and tolerably simple matter; to regulate, directly or indirectly, the personal actions of those subjects is an infinitely complicated matter.
It is one thing to secure to each man the unhindered power to pursue his own good; it is a widely different thing to pursue the good for him. To do the first efficiently, the State has merely to look on while its citizens act; to forbid unfairness; to adjudicate when called on; and to enforce restitution for injuries. To do the last efficiently, it must become an ubiquitous worker — must know each man’s needs better than he knows them himself — must, in short, possess superhuman power and intelligence. Even, therefore, had the State done well in its proper sphere, no sufficient warrant would have existed for extending that sphere; but seeing how ill it has discharged those simple offices which we cannot help consigning to it, small indeed is the probability that it will discharge well offices of a more complicated nature.
Between these law-made agencies and the spontaneously-formed ones, who then can hesitate? The one class are slow, stupid, extravagant, unadaptive, corrupt, and obstructive: can any point out in the other, vices that balance these? It is true that trade has its dishonesties, speculation its follies. These are evils inevitably entailed by the existing imperfections of humanity. It is equally true, however, that these imperfections of humanity are shared by State-functionaries; and that being unchecked in them by the same stern discipline, they grow to far worse results.
Given a race of men having a certain proclivity to misconduct…the question is, whether a society of these men shall be so organized that ill-conduct directly brings punishment, or whether it shall be so organized that punishment is but remotely contingent on ill-conduct? Which will be the most healthful community — that in which agents who perform their functions badly, immediately suffer by the withdrawal of public patronage; or that in which such agents can be made to suffer only through an apparatus of meetings, petitions, polling-booths, parliamentary divisions, cabinet-councils, and red-tape documents? Is it not an absurdly utopian hope that men will behave better when correction is far removed and uncertain than when it is near at hand and inevitable? Yet this is the hope which most political schemers unconsciously cherish…what they propose to have done, they assume the appointed agents will do. That functionaries are trustworthy is their first postulate. Doubtless could good officers be ensured, much might be said for officialism; just as despotism would have its advantages could we ensure a good despot.
Hence then the fact, that while the one order of means is ever failing, making worse, or producing more evils than it cures, the other order of means is ever succeeding, ever improving. Strong as it looks at the outset, State-agency perpetually disappoints every one. Puny as are its first stages, private effort daily achieves results that astound the world.
Where, then, is the warrant for the constantly proposed extensions of legislative action?...In a large class of cases, government measures do not remedy the evils they aim at…in another large class, they make these evils worse instead of remedying them…in a third large class, while curing some evils they entail others, and often greater ones; if…public action is continually outdone in efficiency by private action; and if… private action is obliged to make up for the shortcomings of public action…what reason is there for wishing more public administrations? The advocates of such may claim credit for philanthropy, but not for wisdom; unless wisdom is shown by disregarding experience.
If, where a fair share of intelligence might be expected to lead them right, legislators and their officers go so wrong, how terribly will they err where no amount of intelligence would suffice them — where they must decide among hosts of needs, bodily, intellectual, and moral, which admit of no direct comparisons; and how disastrous must be the results if they act out their erroneous decisions.
May we celebrate Herbert Spencer’s birthday by remembering his insights that most of the modern world seems to have almost completely forgotten.